Thursday, February 27, 2014

Reuse! Architectural design in Capetown

You have to see this!

This is a group of grain silos in Capetown South Africa.  Yup, 42 silos, standing 180 feet high, each only about 18 feet across.  Concrete with a steel frame.

Closed in 1995, it's been chosen for redevelopment as the Zeitz Museum of Contemporary African Art and oh, it is so (potentially) beautiful.  Thomas Heatherwick's architectural firm has released these images of the redesigned 6,000m2 gallery space in a 9000 m2 complex:


I'm in love with the atrium which really preserves the silo tubes as architectural space.

There's obviously a lot more underlying these ideas of reusing before removing.  I've been following Detroit's discussion very closely as they track blightrehab houses, and give away houses.  I'm always looking at MassMoCA and their use of the Arnold Print mill/Sprague Electric Co. facilities.

Think about your boxes, world.  We can be revolutionary.



Monday, February 24, 2014

Probably get in trouble for saying this...A post on the sale of art

Lately, as brought to my attention by a friend who is an alumna of Randolph College when it was Randolph-Macon Woman’s College, a 1912 painting by American Ashcan School artist George Bellows was sold to the National Gallery in London, bringing in $25.5 million dollars which was applied to the institutional endowment.  There's a good summary of the controversy here in Inside Higher Ed.
The issues here are complex.  When art is left to a college or university, it can be done in a number of ways.  Sometimes the work is actually given in trust, so that there are constraints on the gift.  Often when this happens it is because the donor wants the art to enhance the educational experience of the students, faculty, and community of the college.  It is not about giving money.  (However, even in these situations, because there is always a valuation for taxes, there's never the suggestion that art is without a monetary value...)  Sometimes, the works are given, as is the case with this work, without a trust; the college owned the work outright.  It was part of the collection in the Maier Museum on campus, however.  I suspect, although I do not know for sure, that this was done because at the time of gift it made sense to put such an important piece of art on display as part of the educational experience (which is way better than just sticking it in an administrative office for personal enjoyment) and the museum had the facilities to care and store it (convenience).  This clearly leads to a blurring of the ownership in question as the recommended policy by the College Art Association and the American Association of Museums (among others) is that artworks should be sold only to enhance collection acquisitions and maintenance in other art areas; the money should not leave the art institution but be put back in for new uses.  Sale of artwork is a legitimate way to invigorate a collection or to protect other holdings or to move the mission of the museum forward.

This is NOT a new issue.  This sale joins Brandeis's 2009 announcement that it would sell all 6,000 works art after severe financial hardships rocked their endowment; this proposed plan rocked the news for weeks, prompting lawsuits (under what conditions was the art held and were sales legal?) and indignation and retrenching on the position.  It joins pressure on the University of Iowa to sell their Jackson Pollock, insured at $140 million, to repair the institution after severe flooding.  And of course, we must add the issue of Detroit's Institute of Art collection and the city's bankruptcy.

At the heart of the issue is how we value art.  We value it for itself: for its ability to make us think or dream or cry, for its technical virtuosity or curiosity, for its passing through the life of a talented person, for its connection to our culture at a particular time and place. We value what we can learn from interacting with a work directly, rather than from a reproduction.  And yet! We live in a monetary economy where insurance and security and access all require monetary participation.  We have to also put a price on the art in order to participate in that world.  So while art is worth whatever some schmuck will pay for it, it's worth something in equivalent monetary terms.  There's also a tendency to look to that monetary value when we're desperate.  It's not possible to get the same value from almost anything else in the college's ownership.  No one wants old physics texts and selling land (something my graduate institution did a lot) makes you a real estate speculator (with other ramifications on your educational mission).

Do I wish Randolph College could have kept their Bellows (and the other works that no one talks about that were also slated for sale/have already been sold, including Edward Hicks' "A Peaceable Kingdom," Ernest Hennings' "Through the Arroyo" and Rufino Tamayo's "Troubador.”)?  You betcha.  I don't believe that art's monetary price is actually equivalent to its cultural value.  I cannot personally put a price on its cultural value; how much should inspiration cost? how much for outrage that makes us think?  I also believe that having the Bellows was a part of the experience for students that is irrevocably lost and that is tremendously sad.

Stressing that I have NO personal connection to the college and cannot adequately assess value because I believe there is also a value to college experience that can't be rendered in money, Randolph College may have made the sale more palatable for me in a couple of ways. 1) The sale went to the National Gallery of Art in London, a public institution with an educational mission.  Had the sale removed the work entirely from public access by selling to a private collector, I certainly would have felt differently.  One might even argue that removing it from the College is a boon in terms of sheer numbers of people who could see it now.  I'm not entirely convinced by the breadth-vs-depth argument but it is certainly there.  2) The College did work to establish a connection with the National Gallery that is beneficial on both sides: there will be lectures at the College by members of the museum community and students will have internship opportunities at the museum.  There is an educational value that goes with the Bellows piece.

And 3) which is the hardest for me:  $25.5 million dollars could buy a lot of educational experience that might not otherwise be had.  If I trusted the College, the good that could be done with the money in terms of scholarships/aid/enhanced programs, might be worth it.  I see students every year who leave after 1 year (or even 1 semester) having not gotten enough financial aid to make it.  This is a blow to their life experience that cannot be made up by 1 work of art, or even a whole museum.  If this money enhanced the College's ability to really be a stronger institution, it might be worth it.  (I say "if" and "trust" because there is plenty of suggestion that Randolph is struggling to find its footing, after its feeling that switching to co-education would solve all of its problems)

I can't advocate FOR selling art to solve monetary problems when that art is put into the public trust for public experience (different when it's a private collection).  But I have a hard time always arguing AGAINST.

An update--The AAMD sanctions the Meier Museum for monetizing its collection.

Tuesday, February 18, 2014

Art imitates Art imitates Art


The Han Dynasty was a very stable dynasty, lasting in two periods for about 400 years.  It was a time of expansion, established Confucianism, poetry, literature and diplomacy.  China also controlled the trade routes through the Taklamakan Desert (the Silk Road), thus bringing in tremendous prosperity.  In part as a result of both Confucianism (and its connection to ancestor worship) and tremendous trade, very hard stoneware ceramics flourished in the Han Dynasty.
 

Artist Ai Weiwei, one of the most important artists of the last few decades (not just because he's coming from the context of China and its repressive regime), has taken Han Dynasty vases and reimagined them.  As brightly colored dipped works.  My favorite, stamped with the Coca-Cola logo, parallels for me the take-over by modern American consumerism of everything. 
As the Hirshhorn puts it: "In this and other works in which the artist destroys the old to create the new, such as “Coca-Cola Vase” (2007) and his ongoing series of “Colored Vases,” Ai raises questions about the definition and endurance of cultural value."

Ai Weiwei then created a photographic triptych of an event in which he drops a Han Dynasty urn.  Ai draws our attention to what makes value--we value these vases precisely because of their age; they are of dubious quality and they are ubiquitous (precisely because of the circumstances of their creation). 

On Sunday, February 16, artist Maximo Caminero walked in to the Perez Art Museum in Miami, took one of the vase works from Ai's According to What? installation and smashed it.  He has been charged with criminal mischief for breaking the vase, valued at $1 million.  Caminero told the police/press: "I did it for all the local artists in Miami that have never been shown in museums here," he says. "They have spent so many millions now on international artists. It's the same political situation over and over again. I've been here for 30 years and it's always the same."

Caminero says that it was spontaneous (the museum says premeditated), that he didn't really think about the value of Ai's work.  The value question is again raised--is it $1,000,000 because of the Han vase's value, the value that it has as a work by Ai, the value it has as one part of a multiple work installation, and/or the value the insurance company insists it have when exhibited?  Ai's response was that he should have found another means of protest, because of the trouble it will bring Caminero, but that the vase is gone and he expresses calm with that.  Other artists, many upset with Perez Art Museum's policy of passing over local artists, seem to support Caminero's act, feeling it was in connection with Ai's own work. 

Caminero's own work will receive more attention because of his act of vandalism.  But what he has done is the equivalent of a child kicking someone because he is thwarted--it brings the wrong attention in greater measure than the correct attention.  Will the Perez Art Museum look at its exhibition policies? (They are currently hosting the work of Edouard Duval-Carrie, a Haitian born but Miami based artist; I can't delve their history enough to know whether Caminero's protest is valid.)  Sometimes we feel just like children who can't get parents' attention.  Desecration and destruction are one way to draw that kind of attention.


Monday, February 10, 2014

Monuments Men: The Salvation and Conservation of American Image

This is a response essay to the 2014 film, Monuments Men.  It is NOT a review of the movie.  It does however, broadly discuss ideas related to the film and as such does mention scenes.  I tried hard not to write spoilers but your definition may vary.

Also--I will point out--the ideas and errors are my own.


I recently watched Monuments Men, directed by and starring George Clooney.  Based on a true story (Robert Edsel, The Monuments Men: Allied Heroes, Nazi Thieves and the Greatest Treasure Hunt in History, Center Street, 2010) an international team of art historians and architects and “regular” soldiers form the backbone of the search for Nazi looted art at the end of World War II.  The movie has many problems—not just Clooney’s direction that makes a movie that cannot decide if it is a war picture, a heist movie, a buddy flick, and several other genres—but most glaring is the lack of historical accuracy, served with a dazzle of American patriotism.

The premise of the team is a “big idea”—that art is what makes us stand apart as civilizations.  Art is what makes us “truly” human, what allows us to transcend our pedestrian lives and petty quarrels.  The line is repeated over and over: this is an important mission because of the value of Art.  I’m an art historian; on some level, I believe this.  Art is what we make to tell our cultural story, values, concerns, and fears.  (And as such, it includes ephemera and pop culture and music and films. Not just the Michelangelos.)  But it is certainly an arguable position—are paintings more or less valuable than the lives of soldiers and civilians?  Who gets to decide?

Hollywood’s Monuments Men exist in an idealized space.  They exist in a war without individual looting.  Soldiers (of all armies) have always carried off small objects—flags, pins, uniforms, ephemera; they are part of a memorializing process that links the objects to events and places and people and indeed, are part of how we come to terms with the acts and demands of war.  Our magpie eye is also attracted to shiny and beautiful things, as evidenced by stories like Fred Butts who served in 1945 with the battalion which looted Hitler’s chalet, the Eagle’s Nest (Charlotte Sun newspaper, Port Charlotte, Fla. on Monday, September 27, 2010). But Allied soldiers looted works of art as part of this process of repatriation.  The Quedlinburg treasure is one of the most glaring examples; eight works from the lot hidden to protect it were probably stolen by First Lt. Joe T. Meador who was on guard during their rediscovery in 1945.  Meador likely knew well the value of what he had taken; he graduated with a BA in art from North Texas State University.  The case was dropped in 1949 when Quedlinburg became part of East Germany.  Works began to resurface in the 1980s in Texas after Meador’s death and became the focus of legal attention to return the stolen property (William H. Honan, “A Trove of Medieval Art Turns Up in Texas”, NYT 6/14/90).  Hollywood ignored the question of looting on any level.

Hollywood largely ignored the complicated questions of repatriation of stolen art.  At one point, Matt Damon’s character, James Granger, simply picks up a work from a storehouse of Jewish possessions and returns it to the apartment on the label on the back; the apartment is, of course, horrifyingly empty with Juden graffiti on the wall but of course, he can see where the work used to hang and he puts it back on the wall.  This whole scene is supposed to show us how sincere he is when he says he intends the return to rightful owners.  The road to Hell is still paved with good intentions.  The scene indeed implies that it will be an easy job—just look at the back and take the painting there. Cate Blanchett’s character, Jeu de Paume staff member Claire Simone, admonishes him by emphasizing the empty apartment but Clooney’s filmmaking buries this in the characters’ relationship and the over-arching motif of earnest intentions.  600,000 works of art, in a sea of furniture, dishes, clothing, shoes, hair, teeth.  At a hearing in 2006, some 100,000 are still listed as missing (https://plone.unige.ch/art-adr/cases-affaires/liberation-of-saint-peter-from-prison-2013-feldmann-heirs-and-private-person/review-of-the-repatriation-of-holocaust-art-assets-in-the-united-states/view). Almost 70 years later, there are works still in dispute.  How do you return a work when the owner, the owner’s immediate and extended families are wiped out?  How do you prove ownership when all your papers and photographs were destroyed after your family was forced to flee or sent to the camps?

Hollywood isolated the Soviets as the systematic “bad guys” of the world, looking to make a quick profit in their sweep of found Nazi art into their own collections.  Matt Damon’s character, Garner, makes an offhand reference to the Soviets as having lost 20,000,000 people, as an excuse for their behavior, which Clooney’s character dismisses; the film makes the Soviets villains second only to the Nazis who not only stole art but also destroyed it rather than lose it to the Allies.  Systematic military intention to take works of art and move them into the Soviet museums is well documented. However, there is no denying that in the post-war period art entered the international markets when owners could not be easily found, and for those with ready cash, these works entered both private and museum collections.  Various museums have listed works of questionable provenance linked to the Nazi era (Metropolitan Museum: 393 works, Art Institute of Chicago: over 500 works, National Gallery of Art: 400 European paintings). Beginning in 1998 there has been a concerted effort towards acknowledging these works, tracing these works, and returning when possible. The Nazi Era Provenance Project (http://www.nepip.org) is a searchable database of works created before 1946 that changed hands to American museums between 1932 and 1945.  It currently has 28943 objects and 175 museum participants.  It is a step in the right direction but as has been frequently noted, it does not include dealer records or international museum records; other countries keep separate records, keeping searching limited.  Major museums, such as the Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York, devote staff and resources to provenance research, an area growing alongside a global art market, global art trafficking, and continued wars.  As late as 2012, with the find in the home of Cornelius Gurlitt, however, new caches of Nazi-looted pieces are still being discovered.  Did dealers, collectors, and curators know that these works were likely looted? The market of the post-war years clearly suggests that they knew but were deterred by the difficulties (and impossibilities) of returning works and dazzled by the allure of acquiring these artistic masterworks.

Why does any of this matter?  Could you just dismiss this whole essay as the ramblings of another cranky historian? Certainly.  But it matters because the Taliban attacked the giant Buddha statues at Bamiyan in 2001, destroying a cultural heritage because they considered the works idols, contrary to their religious teaching.  It matters because during times of civil war, archaeological sites go unprotected and unguarded, and works of precious value slip away from towns like Balkh in Northern Afghanistan (http://news.nationalgeographic.com/news/whos-stealing-afghanistan-cultural-treasures/).  It matters because at times of political unrest, works are raided, damaged, and stolen as in Mallawi Egypt, perhaps never to be seen again (http://news.nationalgeographic.com/news/2013/08/pictures/130823-museum-mallawi-egypt-looting-artifacts-archaeology-science-antiquities/); the Egyptian Antiquities Museum on Tahrir Square struggles in the instability of the climate, with reports varying about looting, thefts, and security.  If art matters, and I hold this as the tenet of the movie with which I do agree, then how we tell the story of the Nazis and their looted art matters.

What Clooney could have done with a few text slides at the end of the film was set the historical record straight from the inspirational story.  He could have acknowledged the magnitude in numbers of works stolen, the difficulties of restoring works to owners, and the efforts underway to do so.  He chose not to.  He chose to let his story stand.  So his story is simple in a world where we actually need the complex.  His story is one of unalloyed heroism and virtue, with America as the driving force of cultural right. If his story is the one we tell ourselves, then we underestimate the rapaciousness of power to sweep through culture as well as people; we miss the desperation that forces people to sell or abandon their cultural heritage; we miss the lessons that we could have learned about guarding and restoring patrimony. We are instead condemned to repeat these lessons. We are strong enough to be told the whole story.





Reviving a dead blog

What better image than Jean Antoine Houdon's 1787 image Winter?
Because...What the heck?
This was the random artwork of the day generated by the Metropolitan Museum of Art that arrived in my mailbox this morning.
I know that aesthetics have changed.  Even Houdon was breaking tradition with his shivering girl (an alternate title):
The boldness and severity of this image is almost as shocking now as when an earlier, marble version was first shown in the sculptor's studio during the Salon of 1783. As a contemporary observed when it was rejected for the 1785 Salon, "an entirely nude figure is not as indecent as one draped with false modesty."
I don't find a lot of things offensive but I was angry about this one.  Houdon's deliberate prurience, his desire for this body despite its helplessness, his taking away her face to make her anonymous (almost ashamed).  Not sure what the contemporary sees as "false modesty".  This is indecent to me because she's so obviously a fetish, an object for the gaze.

Stick to portraits of Voltaire, Monsieur Houdon.  There we can agree.